Some paradoxes resolved

What does it mean to resolve (or explain) a paradox?

We are not looking for a mathematical demonstration solving the problem at hand.
For example, in the paradox of Achilles and the tortoise, we know that Achilles will reach the tortoise.
We can solve the problem simply through a mathematical formula.

The solution to a paradox is showing the fault in the paradox formulation, or reasoning.
It is the answer to the question: “How does the paradox formulation misrepresent logic?”.

 

The 'coin rotation' paradox

The Zeno paradoxes:  1. Achilles and the Tortoise, 2. The Dichotomy, 3. The Moving Rows, 4. The Arrow.

The 'two envelope exchange' paradox

The Bentley paradox

The Fermi paradox

 

Explanation of the Coin rotation paradox:

The moving coin completes one full revolution after only going half the way around the stationary coin.

Start with two identical coins touching each other on a table, and oriented the same way.

Keep one coin stationary (the eagle) and rotate the other coin (the head) around the eagle coin, keeping a point of contact with no slippage. As the head coin reaches the opposite side, the two coins will again be oriented the same way; The head coin has made one full revolution, while it has only gone half the way around the eagle coin.

coin rotation paradox

Explanation:

This is not a paradox, but a useful example for explaining simple relativity.

Movement (in our case rotation) has meaning only when defined with respect to a system of reference.

We spontaneously tend to choose ourselves, or the room, the table, our eyes, or the eagle coin, as the system of reference, which is case a), below.

However, this is only one of the possible choices:

a) If the system of reference chosen is the eagle coin, then the head coin rotates a complete turn, from facing the eagle to facing away from the eagle.

b) If the system of reference chosen is the head coin, then the eagle coin rotates a complete turn, from the left, to the right.

This could be better verified if you place the coins in a small table and ask a friend to rotate the head coin, while you are moving around the table one complete turn, synchronously with the head coin.

c) Finally, if the system of reference chosen is the contact point, then both coins rotate half a turn, both ending upside-down. In this case, if you keep rotating in synch with the contact point, then you will end on the other side of the table.

What remains constant, in all cases, is the apparent movement of the contact point: it moves along both coins along the top half of the edge of both coins (i.e. half the circumference of each coin).

If you continued the rotation for an additional equal amount, the contact point would reach the original position, having traveled one full circumference in both coins. At that point both coins would be in the original relative position.


The Zeno Paradoxes:

1. Explanation of the 'Achilles and the tortoise' paradox, attributed to Zeno:

When Achilles reaches the point where the tortoise was, the tortoise has advanced further ahead. When Achilles reaches this new point, the tortoise has again advanced, thus Achilles will never reach the tortoise.

An introduction to this 'paradox' is at: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Zeno%27s_paradoxes

zeno

We need to note that Zeno's proposition invites the solver to do a series of steps each time changing his system of reference:

The starting system of reference,

then the new system of reference where Achilles has reached the point where the tortoise started,

then again a new point where the tortoise was, etc.,

every time essentially re-creating the original problem at a smaller scale.

After Zeno's proposed first step, or first change of system of reference, the problem is exactly the same as the original, the only change
being a difference in "scale". Hence the "solver" has no hope of ever progressing towards a solution by following Zeno's suggested steps.

Changing system of reference essentially "restarts" the problem-solving procedure, the proposed "algorithm". That is Zeno's trick.

That is, any problem must be solved using one system of reference.

The solution of Zeno's paradox can be summarized by the following statement:

"Zeno proposes observing the race only up to a certain point in spacetime and then he asks us to stop and restart observing the race using a different system of reference.
This procedure violates the principles of general relativity, thus it is incorrect and must be rejected."

Similarly, you cannot use English measures and in the middle of calculations switch to metric measures.

 

2. The Dichotomy Paradox, attributed to Zeno:

Another of Zeno's paradoxes, the Dichotomy paradox, also described at: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Zeno%27s_paradoxes
can be explained in the same way as the Achilles paradox above.

3. The Moving Rows Paradox, attributed to Zeno:

moving rows 

Zeno uses the same trick, a change of the system of reference, in the moving rows paradox.

First he compares the speed at which the second row of bodies are passing the steady row of bodies,
using the system of reference of the steady row (or the ground), and this speed is: v.

Then he compares the speed at which the same second row of bodies are passing the third row of bodies,
using the system of reference of the moving row, and this speed is: 2v.

He then argues that: v = 2v.

4. Explanation of the Arrow Paradox, Attributed to Zeno:

In the arrow paradox, Zeno uses the example of an arrow in flight. He states that for motion to occur, the arrow must change the position which it occupies, but for every such position we see no motion, thus motion does not exist.

Modern formulation: (See: https://bit.ly/2v30Q8X) "If everything is motionless at every instant, and time is entirely composed of instants, then motion is impossible."

As reported by Aristotle: "If everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest,
and if that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment,
the flying arrow is therefore motionless."

Explanation:

The concept of infinity helps us with mathematical functions “at the limit”, but it is possibly confusing when, in the physical world, we need to evaluate motion (from point A to point B) or speed (an interval of space divided an interval of time).

The term infinite means “not finite”.

A finite interval (of space, or time), can be thought of as the sum of a finite number of very small intervals, as small as we want (infinitesimal), but each with its own dimension.

Conversely, an infinite number, of dimensionless points or instants cannot add up to a finite interval(1).

In the first case, we can calculate the intervals of space and time, thus we can evaluate motion and speed. In the second case, we can’t.

Zeno, in Aristotle’s words, asks us to use the concept of a dimensionless(2) instant to imagine the arrow “at rest”. We can imagine such a snapshot of the arrow, but we cannot evaluate its state of motion.

In other words, by looking only at that dimensionless instant, without measurements of time and space, we cannot evaluate if, or in which direction, the arrow may be moving.

However, Zeno suggests that we could evaluate the arrow’s locomotion at any such moment and declare it motionless. Thus, Zeno’s syllogism breaks down.

We could explain this contradiction to Zeno a bit more figuratively: We distinguish between a snapshot of the arrow, taken at one instant in time, and the arrow it depicts.

Zeno transfers the motionlessness we observe on the snapshot of the arrow, to the arrow that is the subject of the snapshot. This is not a valid logic operation, at any time.

Now, Zeno may respond that he knows nothing about photography, and that he is talking about the real arrow, as we imagine it in a dimensionless instant in time.

We can then respond by saying that, if we are given information about an arrow in a dimensionless instant, and no other space/time information, we cannot say that the arrow is motionless, even if we can imagine it motionless.

NOTES:
(1) An infinite series can never complete, and form a finite interval. It can converge, or get arbitrarily close to, but not actually equal a finite sum.
(2) If that instant had measurable dimensions, we could measure the corresponding intervals of space and time, and calculate the speed of the arrow, invalidating the premise.



Explanation of the "two envelope exchange" paradox

We are shown two envelopes: One envelope contains twice as much money as the other.

Having chosen one envelope, before inspecting it, we are given a chance to take the other envelope instead.

It would appear that it is to our advantage to switch envelopes if we reason as follows:

1. Let’s suppose that the amount in our selected envelope is $20.
2. The probability that it is the smaller amount is 50%, and that it is the larger amount is also 50%.
3. The other envelope may contain either twice as much ($40) or half as much ($10).
4. If we switch envelope, then we could gain $20, or lose $10. Thus we are better off by switching envelopes.

We know that the above reasoning is wrong, because after switching envelopes we could use the same reasoning to switch the envelopes again!

So, how do we solve this apparent paradox?

You may want to think about it, before reading any further.

envelope

A Simple Solution:

We do not know the amount on the selected envelope. However, we know that the total amount in both envelopes is fixed and pre-established.

We can suppose that our selected envelope contains any amount (e.g., $20).

This supposition implies that the total amount for the two envelopes would be either ($20+$10=$30) or ($20+$40=$60).

The key point is that the two totals cannot be true at the same time.

Thus each hypothetical scenario must be analyzed separately, and not as in points 3. and 4. above.

In the first scenario (Total = $30), our supposition that our selected envelope contains $20 would imply that the other envelope contains $10. However, it is equally probable that the opposite is true: our selected envelope could contain only $10 and the other $20.

In both cases, by switching the envelope, we may gain or we may lose $10.

Similarly, in the second scenario (Total = $60), our supposition that our selected envelope contains $20 would imply that the other envelope contains $40. However, it is equally probable that the opposite is true: our selected envelope could contain $40 and the other $20.

In both cases, by switching the envelope, we may gain or we may lose $20.

Thus, in both scenarios, there is no probabilistic advantage in switching envelopes.

 

Explanation of the Bentley paradox:

An introduction to this 'paradox' is at: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bentley%27s_paradox

galaxies

This would be true only if the (observable) universe, as a whole, would be without inherent motion, with respect to a 'bigger' universe.

However, if the observable universe, just like a solar system or a galaxy, is also rotating, then Bentleys assumption does not apply.

The explanation of a rotating observable universe is consistent with the "black hole" or "multiverse" cosmological models.

 

Explanation of the Fermi paradox:

Enrico Fermi realized that due to the sheer number of stars and planets in our galaxy, another civilization in the universe would have had enough time to colonize our entire galaxy and leave an imprint that we could detect. This seems to be logical. Why then we have not seen any such evidence?

An introduction to this 'paradox' is at: https://www.seti.org/seti-institute/project/details/fermi-paradox and https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=sNhhvQGsMEc

spaceship 

A basic assumption of the paradox is unfounded: The Fermi paradox formulation, and the Drake equations, assume that finding a habitable planet, as far as environmental conditions, implies finding life on those planets with a certain probability.

However, the Fermi paradox formulation considers space, matter and time for colonization, without considering the time necessary for life to randomly form anywhere.

With simple probability math, we can calculate the minimum time necessary for the simplest bacterium to develop by random mutations. If such random mutations happen once a second, that time would be more than 1020 seconds. This is assuming the best environmental conditions in a particular “spot” in spacetime. See: bit.ly/1nKG0Pb

The problem is that, according to today’s best scientific knowledge, the observable universe is less than 1018 seconds old.

Random mutations are the only mechanism proposed so far (if we exclude intelligent design) for the evolution of life.

Thus, given the age of the universe and our current scientific knowledge, we conclude that even the simplest bacterium could not have developed anywhere in the observable universe; far less higher forms of life traveling around in spaceships.

 

 

Back to MrGori.com - Go to: Riverpool.com